Davis
& Pérusse’s Classification of Numerical Competence
Davis and Pérusse
(1988) distinguish several types of numerical competence and
suggest that different cognitive or perceptual processes
underlie each type. They divide numerical competence into the
categories of relative numerousness judgments, subitizing,
estimation, and counting.
They assume that relative
numerousness judgments involve the simplest decision
processes since no knowledge of absolute number is required.
Instead an animal judges numerical inequalities that are
ordered in magnitude (e.g. "more" vs.
"less" decisions). In this chapter, the term "numerosity
discrimination" is used instead of relative numerousness
judgments.
Subitizing is
a form of pattern recognition that is used to rapidly assess
small quantities of items. A label is then assigned to the
perceived array. For instance, a glimpse of several dots
arranged at the angles of an imaginary triangle leads to a
judgment about the specific quantity. For us, that quantity
would be labeled "3" because we know that triangles
have three corners. For an animal, that quantity might simply
be labeled "correct amount – peck it!" without the
animal necessarily knowing how this quantity relates to other
numerical values. Other researchers doubt there is a separate
subitizing process however (see section VI on Models and
Mechanisms for Numerical Processing).
Estimation
refers to the ability to assign a numerical label to an array
of large numbers of items without having to count or enumerate
each one. When we judge at a glance that there are about 50
ducks on a lake we are "estimating". Animals’
judgments of large number arrays have not been systematically
studied yet.
Counting is
the ability to discriminate the absolute number in a set by a
process of enumeration. This involves tagging each item in a
set, and applying a series of ordered labels as these items
are ‘counted off’. To count the number of peanuts in a
packet of mixed nuts, for instance, we might put each peanut
to one side, at the same time labelling them "1",
"2", "3", etc. The numerical label we
apply to the last peanut we find is the absolute or cardinal
number of peanuts in the packet. The criteria for counting
behavior have been defined by Gelman and Gallistel (1978) (see
section IV on Cardinal Numbers and Counting). Davis and
Pérusse regard counting as a more complex process than the
ones involved in relative numerousness judgments or subitizing
(and presumably estimation too).
They also discuss the
concept or sense of number as an attribute of
counting. This term implies an ability to transfer numerical
discriminations across sensory modalities (e.g. 5 sound pulses
are equivalent to 5 light flashes) or across modes of
presentation (e.g. 4 red squares shown simultaneously on a
computer screen are equivalent to 4 red squares presented one
after the other). |